9 Raising versus control


In Chapter 4, we introduced subject movement from Spec(VP) to Spec(IP). In this chapter, we address a related type of movement known as subject raising. Both ordinary subject movement and subject raising affect subjects of sentences, but they differ in how far the subject moves. With ordinary subject movement, the subject remains in its own clause, whereas with subject raising, the subject moves out of its own clause into a higher one; the clause out of which the subject moves is always nonfinite. The demonstration that English has subject raising relies on the existence of a special class of noun phrases, and we therefore begin our discussion of subject raising with them. We then show that certain verbs trigger subject raising, and we present an analysis of it. We conclude by distinguishing raising from a superficially similar phenomenon called control.

Special subjects

English has three types of noun phrases whose distribution is restricted by comparison to ordinary noun phrases: What makes these noun phrases special is that they are subject to strict locality requirements. In particular, they must be licensed as subjects of an appropriate (Fregean or Aristotelian) predicate. What we mean by this is that each of the special noun phrases is ungrammatical unless it is the subject of the appropriate predicate. Here and throughout this section, special subjects are in italics. Predicates that license the special subjects are in green; ones that don't are in red.

Expletive there

The first special subject is expletive there. As already mentioned in
Chapter 3, expletive there is only grammatical when the main verb of its clause belongs to a certain class of verbs---roughly speaking, verbs of being in existence or coming into existence.

(1) a. ok After their military defeat, there arose among the Plains tribes a powerful spiritual movement.
b. ok There is a problem.
c. ok There began a reign of terror.
d. ok In the end, there emerged a new caudillo.
e. ok There ensued a period of unrest and lawlessness.
f. ok There exists an antidote.
g. ok There follows a section on the care of gerbils.
h. ok There has occurred an unfortunate incident.
i. ok There remains a single course of action.
(2) a. * There continued the same problem.
b. * There failed an available time slot.
c. * There proved toxins in the soap.
d. * There rang the mail carrier.
e. * There seems no solution.
f. * There sang an impressive choir from Russia.
g. * There turns out an antidote.

Subject idiom chunks

The second type of special subjects are subject idiom chunks (that is, the subjects of sentential idioms like those in (3)).

(3) a.   The cat has got X's tongue.
b.   The cat is out of the bag.
c. The fur will fly.
d. The jig is up.
e. The pot is calling the kettle black.

What will be crucial for our purposes is that the subjects in (3) have whatever idiomatic force they have only in connection with the rest of the idiom, but not otherwise. For instance, neither cat in (3b) nor pot in (3e) have a metaphorical sense of secret or hypocrite, respectively, in other syntactic contexts. So although the sentences in (4), unlike those in (2), are not ungrammatical, they have only literal interpretations.

(4) a.   The cat is safe with her.
(can't mean: 'The secret is safe with her.')
b. # Fortunately, the pot retracted that piece of duplicitous slander.
(can't mean: 'The hypocrite retracted that piece of duplicitous slander.')

Weather it

The third type of special subject, weather it, is the subject of verbs of precipitation. The relationship between weather it and the predicates that license it is even closer than in the previous two cases. Not only is weather it licensed by verbs of precipitation, but the verbs of precipitation are in turn themselves licensed by weather it. In other words, weather it stands in a mutual licensing relationship with the verbs of precipitation. As a result, other semantically conceivable subjects are not possible, as the contrast between (5) and (6) shows. We indicate this by putting weather it in italics (indicating its status as a special subject that needs to be licensed) as well as in green (indicating its own status as a licenser).

(5)   ok It is { hailing, pouring, raining, sleeting, snowing. }
(6)   * The { air, atmosphere, environment, precipitation, sky, weather } is { hailing, pouring, raining, sleeting, snowing. }

To summarize, all three types of special subjects are special because they must be licensed in a local relation---specifically, as the subject of a particular type of predicate. Expletive there is licensed as the subject of verbs of being in or coming into existence, subject idiom chunks are licensed as subjects of sentential idioms, and weather it stands in a mutual licensing relation with verbs of precipitation.

Subject raising

Data

Given what we have just said about expletive there, consider the contrast between (7) and (8).

(7) a. * There seems to continue the same problem.
b. * There seemed to ring the mail carrier.
(8) a. ok There seems to be a problem.
b. ok There seems to exist an antidote.

The ungrammaticality of (7) is not surprising, since seem does not belong to the class of verbs that license there; recall (2e), repeated here as (9).

(9)   * There seems no solution.

By the same token, however, the grammaticality of (8) is unexpected.

A first clue to the answer to this puzzle lies in the fact that each of the examples in (7) and (8) contains two verbs, and hence two clauses, rather than just one. In the examples that follow, the lower clause, which is a complement of seem, is enclosed in square brackets. The higher, or matrix, clause contains the bracketed complement clause. Now notice that neither of the complement verbs in (7) licenses there, whereas both of the complement verbs in (8) do. Thus, instead of considering all four sentences in (7) and (8) as parallel to (9), it is more insightful to draw the parallels in (10)-(13). In this view, the fact that seem, the matrix verb in all of the sentences, doesn't license there turns out to be a red herring.

(10) a. * There seems [ to continue the same problem. ]
b. * There continued the same problem.
(11) a. * There seemed [ to ring the mail carrier. ]
b. * There rang the mail carrier.
(12) a. ok There seems [ to be a problem. ]
b. ok There is a problem.
(13) a. ok There seems [ to exist an antidote. ]
b. ok There exists an antidote.

Analogous examples can be constructed for the other two types of special subjects. For instance, the complex sentences in (14) have an idiomatic interpretation, even though the subject idiom chunk appears to be separated from the rest of the idiom.

(14) a.   The cat seems [ to have got X's tongue. ]
b.   The cat proved [ to be out of the bag. ]
c. The fur began [ to fly. ] ]
d. The jig proved [ to be up. ]
e. The pot seems [ to be calling the kettle black. ]

And finally, the contrast between (15) and (16) is parallel to that between (5) and (6).

(15) a. It continued [ to { hail, pour, rain, sleet, snow. } ]
b. It seems [ to be { hailing, pouring, raining, sleeting, snowing. } ]
(16) a. * The { air, atmosphere, environment, precipitation, sky, weather } continued [ to { hail, pour, rain, sleet, snow. } ]
b. * The { air, atmosphere, environment, precipitation, sky, weather } seems [ to be { hailing, pouring, raining, sleeting, snowing. } ]

Analysis

The upshot of the examples in (7)-(16) is that when the matrix clause contains seem or a similar verb, it is possible for the subject of the matrix clause to be licensed by the (more distant) predicate of the complement clause, rather than by the (closer) matrix predicate. We can think of verbs like seem as acting like catalysts, allowing the licensing of subjects, which is ordinarily confined to the same clause, to extend beyond and across clause boundaries. Verbs that act as as catalysts in this regard are called raising verbs.

The term 'raising verb' is potentially confusing. It is not the verb itself that undergoes movement. Rather, it is the complement subject that raises into the matrix clause, as we discuss in detail in a moment. A better term for the verb class in question might therefore be 'subject raising triggers.' However, we will continue to use the term 'raising verb' because it is standard in the literature.

Raising verbs are semantically deficient in not imposing selectional restrictions on the eventual matrix subject. As the contrasts in (17) show, verbs ordinarily select subjects with particular semantic properties. For instance, breathe, elapse, and write select subjects that are animate beings, periods of time, and literate humans, respectively.

(17) a.   The { cat, #rock } is breathing.
b.   More than a { week, #desk } has elapsed.
c.   The { boy, #cockatoo } wrote an essay.

Raising verbs, on the other hand, impose no such selectional restrictions. In fact, there is no reason to think that they are associated with a subject of their own at all. We will represent this fact by associating raising verbs with elementary trees that have no specifier position, as illustrated for seems in (18).

(18)    

We are now in a position to derive a sentence like (8a). The derivation of the complement clause is given in (19). Notice that in (19a), the eventual matrix subject, expletive there, is licensed by virtue of being the specifier of a VP headed by a licensing verb (in this case, be).

(19) a.       b.  
Local (spec-head) licensing of there Substitute (19a) as complement of to

Substituting the structure in (19b) as the complement of the raising verb yields (20a), which in turn becomes the complement of the matrix I element, yielding (20b).

(20) a.       b.  
Substitute (19b) as complement of raising verb Substitute (20a) as complement of matrix I

As it stands, (20b) is not well-formed, and the complement subject must move to the matrix subject position. This movement is motivated because the complement subject has a nominative case feature that cannot be checked in the lower clause. We know that the case feature in question is nominative from contrasts as in (21).

(21) a.   He seems [ to have a problem. ]
b. * Him seems [ to have a problem. ]

The reason that the case feature cannot be checked in the lower clause is that neither Spec(VP) nor the lower Spec(IP) stand in the proper structural relation to a head that checks nominative case. In particular, nonfinite I has no case features at all (recall the ungrammaticality of (30) in Chapter 8), and V as a category checks objective rather than nominative case.1 Unable to receive case within its own IP, then, the complement subject is forced to move to the Spec(IP) of the matrix clause, as shown in (22). In this position, nominative case is checked by the finite I of the matrix clause in the spec-head configuration.

(22)    

It is this movement of the subject from the complement clause to the matrix clause that is called (subject) raising. Notice that the subject first moves within the complement from Spec(VP) to Spec(IP), and only then from the lower Spec(IP) to the higher one. We assume the first step on the grounds that all clauses require a subject in Spec(IP) (recall the subject requirement introduced in Chapter 3). Notice further that the locality constraint on there (according to which it must occupy the specifier position of a licensing verb) is maintained by its trace.

Be careful not to confuse raising verbs with the verbs that license the various kinds of special subjects. Raising verbs don't themselves license special subjects; rather, they are the catalysts that allow an already established relationship between a special subject and its licensing predicate to extend across a clause boundary.

However, although the two classes are distinct from one another, it is possible for a verb to belong to both classes (just as it is possible for a single person to belong to two distinct clubs).

Further evidence for subject raising

By definition, all raising verbs take nonfinite complements. In addition, some (though not all) of these verbs are able to take finite complements headed by the complementizer that, as illustrated in (23).

(23) a.   Itexpl { appears, seems } [ that there is a problem. ]
b.   Itexpl { appears, seems } [ that itweather is raining. ]
c.   Itexpl { appears, seems } [ that the cat is out of the bag. ]

Sentences like those in (23) have two properties that support the analysis of subject raising just presented. First, as we mentioned, raising verbs impose no selectional restrictions on a subject. This is consistent with the fact that the matrix subject in the sentences in (23) is expletive it. In contrast to ordinary subjects, expletive it is semantically empty; that is, it has no properties such as animacy, humanness, and so on. Rather, it satisfies two purely syntactic functions---namely, satisfying the requirement that all clauses have subjects and entering into a case-checking relationship with the matrix I. In other words, it fulfills exactly the same syntactic functions as a subject that has undergone raising. Second, according to the analysis of subject raising just presented, the matrix subject originates in the complement clause and is forced to move because its nominative case feature cannot be checked there. If there were a way for the complement subject's case feature to be checked in the complement clause, we would expect it to be able to remain within the lower clause. As the sentences in (23) show, this is exactly what happens when the complement of the raising verb is a finite clause. The complement subject's case feature can now be checked by finite I within the complement clause, and so there is no need for the complement subject to raise out of its clause.

As we just mentioned, not all subject raising verbs are also able to take finite complements. Tend is one such subject raising verb.
(i) a.   There tend to be traffic jams during rush hour;
itweather tends to rain in Seattle;
the jig tends to be up sooner or later.
b. * Itexpl tends that there are traffic jams during rush hour;
itexpl tends that itweather rains in Seattle;
itexpl tends that the jig is up sooner or later.

Conversely, not all verbs that occur in the construction in (23) are also subject raising verbs.
(ii) a.   Itexpl occurred to me that there is a solution;
itexpl occurred to me that itweather never snows in Lagos;
itexpl occurred to him that the jig was up.
b. * There occurred to me to be a solution;
itweather occurred to me never to snow in Lagos;
the jig occurred to him to be up.

A look-alike: Control

Data

Subject raising verbs are not the only class of English verbs that take nonfinite complements. A second class, the so-called control verbs, is illustrated in (24).

(24)     Larry { attempted, decided, expected, hoped, tried } [ to travel to Bhutan. ]

Superficially, control verbs resemble raising verbs because both types of verbs take nonfinite complement clauses headed by to. However, the two verb classes differ in their syntactic behavior in two important respects. First, control verbs impose selectional restrictions on their subjects. For instance, hope selects a human subject, a requirement that is not met in (25).

(25)   # The chrysalis hoped [ to become a butterfly. ]

Moreover, the restrictions imposed by the control verb are distinct from those imposed by the verb in the lower clause. This is illustrated by (26), where the matrix subject satisfies the selectional restrictions of hope, but not those of elapse.

(26)   # Larry hoped [ to elapse. ]

Further evidence for the semantic independence of the matrix and the complement subjects comes from the subset of control verbs that also allow finite complements. In such cases, the matrix and complement subjects need not refer to the same discourse entity.

(27)     Larry { decided, expected, hoped } ...
a.   ... [ that he would travel to Bhutan. ]
b.   ... [ that { we, she } would travel to Bhutan. ]

It is true, however, that when the complement of a control verb is nonfinite, as it is in (24), the interpretation of the complement subject is constrained in a way that it isn't when the complement is finite, as in (27). Thus, the sentences in (24) with counterparts in (27) can only have the interpretation in (27a), never those in (27b). When the complement of a control verb is nonfinite, the matrix subject can be thought of as fixing or 'controlling' the referent of the complement subject; hence the name of the verb class.

Notice that the counterparts of (27) with raising verbs replacing the control verbs in the matrix clause are completely ungrammatical.

(28) a. * Larry { appears, seems } [ that he has traveled to Bhutan. ]
b. * Larry { appears, seems } [ that { we, she } have traveled to Bhutan. ]

The reason is that nonexpletive subjects like Larry need a semantic role like agent, patient, recipient, and so on. Such semantic roles are associated with verbs, but not with I, and they are assigned to the argument positions of the heads that they are associated with. But since raising verbs have no specifier, and since the complement position in (28) is filled by the that clause, the matrix subjects in (28) end up without a semantic role.

There is a second major difference between raising verbs and control verbs. Since control verbs require their own subject, but do not license any of the special subjects discussed earlier, these special subjects should be ruled out as the subjects of control verbs. This expectation is borne out; the sentences in (29) are either downright ungrammatical or do not allow the relevant idiomatic interpretation.

(29) a. * There { attempted, decided, expected, hoped, tried } [ to be a problem. ]
b. * Itweather { attempted, decided, expected, hoped, tried } [ to rain. ]
c. The cat { attempted, decided, expected, hoped, tried } [ to get X's tongue. ]
(only literal interpretation possible)
d. # The jig { attempted, decided, expected, hoped, tried } [ to be up. ]

Analysis

We now present an analysis of control verbs that captures the syntactic differences between them and raising verbs. As we saw in (25), control verbs, unlike raising verbs, impose selectional restrictions on their subjects. We represent this by including a specifier position in the elementary tree for control verbs, as illustrated for decide in (30). Notice further that the complements of control verbs are CPs, not IPs; we return to this point in a moment.

(30)    

Moreover, as we saw in (26), the verb of the complement clause in a subject control sentence also imposes selectional restrictions on its subject. Therefore, this verb too needs a specifier position, which is occupied by a subject that is distinct from the matrix subject (though it will be coreferential with it). The way we represent this is by assuming that English has a silent pronoun, so-called PRO (read as 'big pro'). It can be thought of as comparable to the 'you understood' of imperative sentences like (31a).

(31) a.   ___ be quiet!
b.   You be quiet!

It is this silent pronoun that occupies Spec(VP) of the control verb's nonfinite complement, as shown in (32), much as an overt pronoun occupies that position in a finite complement (recall (27)). The derivation of the complement clause is shown in detail in (32). As just mentioned, we address the issue of the CP in (32c) in a moment.

(32) a.       b.       c.  
PRO as subject of verb of complement clause Substitute (32a) as complement of to Substitute (32b) as complement of silent complementizer

Substituting the structure in (32c) as the complement of the control verb yields (33a), which in turn becomes the complement of the matrix I element, yielding (33b).

(33) a.       b.  
Substitute (32c) as complement of control verb Substitute (32a) as complement of matrix I

Finally, subject movement of the matrix and complement subjects yields (34). Once again, we assume that PRO moves from Spec(VP) to Spec(IP) in the complement clause on the grounds that every clause has a subject.

(34)    

Why is the complement of decide assigned the category CP rather than IP? The reason is that decide, along with certain other control verbs, allows indirect questions as complements, as in (35).

(35)     Larry must decide [ whether to travel to Bhutan. ]

Since whether is a complementizer, the indirect question in (35) cannot be an IP, but must be a CP, as shown in (36).2

(36)    

For uniformity, we extend this CP analysis to the complements of all control verbs, even to the complements of control verbs such as hope or promise that do not allow indirect question complements.


Notes

1. In principle, seems could check objective case on the complement subject in the head-spec configuration, just as expect and other ECM verbs do. However, the ungrammaticality of (i) shows that seem is not in fact able to do so.

(i)   * Itexpl seems [ him to have a problem. ]

Why seem should differ from the ECM verbs in this way needs to be explained. It has been proposed that there is a correlation between a verb's ability to select the properties of its specifier and its ability to check objective case on its objects. This correlation, known as Burzio's generalization, is discussed further in Chapter 10.

2. It has been argued that whether is not itself a complementizer, but that it occupies the specifier position of a silent complementizer. For present purposes, the exact position of whether (head or specifier) is not important, but only that the entire indirect question is a CP.


Exercises and problems

Exercise 9.1

For this exercise, be sure to provide the evidence (grammatical or ungrammatical sentences) on the basis of which you reach your conclusions. You don't need to include much in the way of discussion beyond that.

A. Using expletive there as your diagnostic, find five raising verbs and five control verbs other than the ones discussed in the last two sections of this chapter.

B. Using expletive there as your diagnostic, find five ECM verbs other than expect (recall Chapter 8).

C. Which of the following statements is correct? (The question concerns expect in the active, not the passive.)

(1) a.   Expect is an ECM verb.
b.   Expect is a raising verb.
c.   Expect is a control verb.
d.   (a) + (b)
e.   (a) + (c)

Exercise 9.2

For this exercise, be sure to provide the evidence (grammatical or ungrammatical sentences) on the basis of which you reach your conclusions. You don't need to include much in the way of discussion beyond that.

A. As mentioned in this chapter, raising verbs are logically distinct from the verbs that license there. There are, however, some verbs that belong to both classes. Can you think of any?

B. As we mentioned in this chapter, there are raising verbs that cannot take finite complements. Can you think of other verbs besides tend that have this property?

Exercise 9.3

For this exercise, you don't need to build trees. You just need to provide the evidence (grammatical or ungrammatical sentences) on the basis of which you reach your conclusions.

The discussion in this chapter was restricted to raising and control verbs, but there are also raising and control adjectives in English. Using expletive there as your diagnostic, classify the adjectives in (1) as raising adjectives, control adjectives, or neither.

(1)     anxious, eager, evident, happy, liable, likely, possible

Exercise 9.4

Using the all purpose grammar tool, build trees for the sentences in (1).

(1) a.   They aren't anxious to move.
b.   They hope to get the job.
c.   They are likely to get the job.
d.   They appear to be lunatics.